
THE IDEOLOGIES
OF SCIENCE Simon Schwartzman
Paper presented to the Research Committee on Science
and Politics, XIIth World Congress of the International Political Science
Association, Rio de Janeiro, August, 1982. Originally published as "Entwicklung
und die Mythen der Wissenschaft", in Weltgesellschaft und Sozialstruktur
(Festschrift für Peter Heintz), Verlag Rüger, 1980.
Introduction
The Old Synthesis: Progress through Science
Thesis: The King Philosopher
a) Scientific planning
b) The intellectuals
Antithesis: The Kingdom of
Science a)
The rationalization of society
b) The Republic of Science
The new synthesis: science, technology and
economic development
Notes
Introduction
Writing in Science in 1966, the late Homi J. Bhabha, the father
of India's nuclear technology, stated a very simple and seemingly convincing
notion about the relationships between science and social and economic development.
"What the developed countries have and the underdeveloped lack is modern
science and an economy based on modern technology. The problem of developing
under-developed countries is therefore the problem of establishing modern
science in them and transforming their economy to one based on modern science
and technology."(1). The detonation of a nuclear device in India,
in 1974, and the launching of a satellite the next year, left no doubt as
to the success of India's strife for proficiency in some of the most sophisticated
areas of modern technology. The question of how far these achievements helped
to lead India into a developed economy, however, is much less clear.
The relationships between science, modern technology and development are
of course much more complex than what Bhabha's statement would let us suppose.
This complexity derives, in fact, from the very complex nature of the host
of activities, institutions, and bodies of knowledge that usually are brought
together under the term "science." More than that, the perceptions
one has of what science is and how it relates to long-range processes of
social transformation is usually tainted by a cloud of myths that have always
surrounded the scientific activity.(2)
These myths are not to be taken lightly. They are not simple misconceptions
that one could expect to be brushed away once knowledge improves and the
correct nature of these relationships become established. A myth, according
to a standard dictionary definition, is "a usually legendary narrative
that presents parts of the beliefs of a people or explains a practice or
natural phenomena." The myths about science are one
of the ways societies perceive and justify their beliefs in progress, and
the way scientists explain and justify their practices. While reality itself
is contradictory and complex, the myths are easy to grasp and have a coherence
that is more related to the social functions they perform than to the actual
canons of formal logic. This means that they do not fit into a coherent
picture, but are often contradictory in their assumptions and implications.
A dialectic-like approach seems appropriate to deal with them. Without any
claim to dialectic orthodoxy, we shall look first into the general, undifferentiated
mythical concept of progress through science, which will be then split into
two, a thesis and an antithesis. The thesis is the Myth of the King Philosopher,
in which we will discuss the notions of scientific planning and the role
of the intellectuals in that. The basic assumption of the thesis is that
scientists are a special kind of intellectuals, who are entitled to and
actually will run society according to their superior knowledge. The antithesis
holds that society tends to rationality on its own, and that the only things
scientists must do is to be loyal to themselves. Thus, we will speak of
the Kingdom of Science, with a special chapter dedicated to the Republic
of Scientists. Finally, there is an attempt of a new synthesis, which are
the theories of the identity between science, technology and development.
To point to these myths is not the same as to denounce them as necessarily
wrong and misleading. What gives strength to a myth is that it captures
a significant portion of the social reality, how it is as well as how people
perceive it, and transforms it into a generalized truth. When it is said,
for instance, that science and technology are two sides of the same coin,
the verb "to be" means that this is so, that it should
be so, and that it will be so whenever science
and technology develop. This combination of empirical, normative and predictive
statements is what makes the myths so elusive, but at the same time so immune
to empirical or logical disproof.
The introduction of modern science outside the Western world has been as
much a consequence of independent social process as a product of political
and social will. This is why the myths play, here, such a large role, which
we will try to spell out in the remainder of this text.
The Old Synthesis: Progress through
Science
Homi Bhabha's statement at the beginning belongs to an old tradition that
maintains that science or superior knowledge is good and socially useful,
and is a key factor in distinguishing between advanced and backward, primate
or barbarian societies. This was clear, it seems, for Jawaharlal Nehru,
who is quoted by Bhabha as a strong supporter of science because of its
role "not only in transforming the material environment, but in transforming
man. It is an inherent obligation of a great country like India, "
said Nehru, "with its traditions of scholarship and original thinking
and its great cultural heritage, to participate fully in the march of science,
which is probably mankind's greatest enterprise today."(3)
The idea that Science, with a capital "S", holds the key to the
solution to the problems of mankind is not, of course, new. Robert K. Merton,
in his classic study on the emergence of modern science in seventeenth~century
England, shows how the increasing prestige of scientific careers was related,
at that time, with the idea that this was both a practical, utilitarian
and a noble kind of endeavor. Arithmetic and geometry, for instance, were
"most useful for keeping accounts and enabling a gentleman to understand
fortifications, " while chemistry was "a piece of knowledge not
misbecoming a gentleman."(4) For the
Puritanic ethics of the time, science, or natural philosophy, "was
instrumental first, in establishing practical proofs of the scientist's
state of grace; second, in enlarging control of nature; and third, in glorifying
God. Science was enlisted in the service of individual, society and deity."(5)
We could, of course, look further back for the source of these ideas, if
we just remember that, for the Greek philosophers not only was knowledge
the most pleasant of the activities, but that, in Plato's Utopia, the Philosopher
is King.
This mixture of moral and pragmatic justifications for scientific activities
is probably the most important dimension of this scientific myth. It has
been, historically, an indispensable ingredient in the culture of all societies
where Science has occurred as a significant activity. Sociologists of science
like to call "scientism" the social and cultural support for scientific
ideals, and there is abundant historical evidence to show that scientism,
when it emerges, tends to be part of the ideologies of rising social groups.
This was, of course, true in the case of Merton's gentlemen of seventeenth-century
England, as it was the case with the French intellectuals in the Eighteenth
century, and the Germans in the Nineteenth.(6)
We can leave aside, in this context, the important question of the social
determinants of this scientific myth, and see what happens when it is present
in a given society. One effect is that some of society's most talented and
gifted individuals choose science as a worthwhile area of activity. The
other is that the society, as a whole, agrees to pay for the costs of scientific
activities. Another characteristic is that science is sought for and supported
irrespective of its practical results. It is not that there is no interest
or expectations about the products of scientific knowledge; on the contrary,
they are a very important component of the myth. But, when the belief is
there, the failure to produce practical results in the short or medium run
is not enough to reduce the faith in the value of scientific research, for
those who do it as well as for those who have staked their support on it.
The whole Western history of the last four centuries seems to be a proof
of the long term benefits of science research, and this gives an important
argument in science's behalf in periods of technological meagerness.
A final consequence of the scientific myth is that the term "Science"
comes to encompass a multiplicity of different and not always really compatible
types of activity. What is and what is not scientific activity is, o course,
an extremely complicated epistemological question, which we could not try
to approach here.(7) It suffices to use a
simple sociological definition - "science is what people who are recognized
as scientists do" - to see the complex array of activities that come
into the same heading. Natural vs, social, empirical vs. exact, basic vs.
applied science, demonstration vs. confirmation, data-gathering vs. theory
construction, research vs. development, science vs. technology - all these
and other dichotomies describe activities which are very different in goals,
styles, methods of verification, criteria of truth and validation. We would
also find big differences if we went across disciplines - what is "basic
science, " for instance, for a physicist, a botanist, a marine biologist
and a geologist? These differences in "working paradigms" are
combined, in turn, with profound differences in the way people organize
themselves for the pursuit of their scientific tasks. Universities, autonomous
research centers, large-scale industrial laboratories, institutes of technology,
academe, the social settings for scientific research can range from small
to gigantic, informal to extremely bureaucratized, academic to completely
committed to technological results, cost-effective to completely cost-innocent
institutions.
Moreover, the myth of progress through science can uncover under its generality
and pervasiveness very different and often contradictory assumptions about
the relationships between science and society. We can consider these assumptions
as mythical in themselves, since they influence how science development
is sought for by different people and institutions. One of these myths has
to do with the role intellectuals and scientists play in their country's
life. The other has to do with the way science, as rational knowledge, makes
its presence felt in the social and political realm.
Thesis: The King Philosopher
a) Scientific planning
Nineteenth century positivism is an excellent expression of the old Platonic's
utopia of a Republic rationally organized and ruled by the men of knowledge.
In his outline of the Travaux Scientifiques Nécessaires pour reformer
la Société, Auguste Compte saw the need of two tasks to be performed:
"l'une, théorique ou spirituelle, a pour but le développement de l'idée-mère
du plan, c'est-a-dire du nouveau principe suivant lequel les relations sociales
doivent être coordonnées, et la formation du système d'idées générales destiné
a servir de guide a la société. L'autre, pratique et temporelle, détermine
le mode de répartition du pouvoir a l'ensemble d'institutions administratives
les plus conformés a l'esprit du système, tel qu'il a été arrêté par les
travaux théoriques. La seconde série étant fondée sur la première, dont
elle n'est que la conséquence et la réalisation, c'est par celle-ci que,
de toute nécessité, le travail général doit commencer."(8)
The first task is to be given to the scientists, "les hommes que font
profession de former des combinaisons théoriques suivies méthodiquement,
c'est-à-dire les savants occupés de l'étude des sciences d'observation"
(p. 86). The second task, the execution of the plan, could then be given
to the managers, or the '"chefs des travaux industriels." The
dominance of the intellectual over the practical chores is absolute: "il
y a, dans ce travail, une parte spirituelle qui doit être traitée la première,
et une partie temporelle qui le sera consécutivement" (p. 88). In a
footnote, Comte takes into account the fact that natural scientists are
often too limited to their fields of specialization, and talks about "les
hommes qui, sans consacrer leur vie à la culture spéciale d'aucune science
d'observation, possèdent la capacité scientifique, et ont fait de l'ensemble
des connaissances positives une étude assez approfondie pour s'être pénétrés
de leur esprit." To these would be reserved "l'activité essentielle
dans la formation de la nouvelle doctrine sociale." The other would
just have a "passive" role (p. 87).
The notion that society should be organized through science is just one
step away from the idea that science itself should be subject to the same
type of planned organization. Comte himself did not hesitate to make this
step, and his mistrust for the scientists who wanted to have their own,
independent institutions, is well known. Comte's king philosopher is not
a simple scientist, but an intellectual, a man that can go beyond the limits
of specific knowledge and attain a grasp of all knowledge, and from there
to derive obeisance and acceptance to their supremacy. He talks about "les
savants," and stresses that "eux seuls exercent, en matière de
théorie, une autorité non contestée .Ainsi, indépendamment de ce que seuls
ils son compétents pour former la nouvelle doctrine organique, ils son exclusivement
investis de la force morale nécessaire pour en déterminer l'admission"
( p. 89). The importance of the positivistic outlook does not lie in its
historical truth nor in its practicality, and less so in its originality.
Its importance resides in the fact that it synthesizes one of the underlying
myths of modern science, and as such has had and still has a great impact.
One should look, for instance, at the rather extreme statements put forward
a few years ago by Stevan Dedijer on the needs for science in the developing
countries:
"The first effective steps along the road of national
development are unthinkable today without using the results of research
from the start. It is impossible to estimate your starting degree of development,
it is impossible to define your objective, it is impossible to make each
step from the first to the second without research in the natural, social
and life sciences... The development of a national research potential,
i.e. , qualified scientists, scientific institutions and equipment and
a scientific culture within those circles must be created in order to
carry out other national policies with any degrees of effectiveness. Sciences
policy must be as important a part of the national development policy
as economic and educational policy and, perhaps, mores important than
foreign, military and other policies. To neglect a planned and vigorous
development of indigenous research in the physical, life and social sciences
endangers the whole process of development."(9)
This need for modern science contrasts very sharply, for the same author,
with the realities of the developing countries. They lack a scientific community,
a government used to deal with science, and "industrial, agricultural,
commercial, educational, medical, military and other institutions that value
the results of research. " They lack the "institutional and motivational
elements for research, " and hence are "basically alien or hostile"
to it.
The solution which is presented to solve the problem is planning, which
is , of course, made much more difficult because of the very lack of scientific
experience and tradition of theses countries. "In underdeveloped countries,
ignorance, prejudice and the absence of sources of reasonable advice render
such decisions (about science) much more difficult, their success much mores
problematic. " These and other problems only lead the author to require
more, rather than less, planning: "every decision on science must be
part of a national plan for the development and use of the results of research.
Sciences must be looked upon as part of a planned national policy. Each
primes minister should establish in his offices a secretary for science."
In fact, agencies and ministries for science policy haves developed throughout
the world in the last fifteen years, and international institutions likes
UNESCO, the Organization for Economic Cooperation and Development, the Organization
of American States) and others created their own structures to help in the
establishment of the national bureaucracies for science planning. Pew or
nones of the most responsible leaders of these organizations would endorse
Dedijer's non-qualified and naive optimism on the power of science and the
virtues of planning; but they will share the same concern and the same basic
distrust about the ability of the scientists themselves to bring to their
countries the benefits that they should. Science planning is today but one
of the structures of comprehensive planning that haves been established
to try to bring development and modernization to the third world. They share,
of course, all problems and difficulties that have plagued these structures.(10)
b) The intellectuals
The intellectual's claim to moral superiority and a right to run society
is not, of course, something that starts with Comte or even Plato. One of
the central themes of Max Weber's studies on the ancient Chinese, Indian
and Jewish societies is the power interplay between the military, that rule
by force, and the intellectuals, that try to rule by moral authority.(11) Historically, intellectuals often emerged as
a group specialized in religious matters. As Max Weber pointed out, "at
first priesthood itself was the most important career of intellectualism,
particularly wherever sacred scriptures existed, which would make it necessary
for the priesthood to become a literary guild engaged in the interpreting
of the scriptures and teaching their content, meaning and application. "
This was particularly trues , still according to Weber, to India , Egypt,
in Islam and ancient and medieval Christianity; and less so in Greece, Rome
and China, places where "the development of all metaphysical and ethical
thought fell into the hands of non-priests, as did the development of theology."(12)
In China, Confucianism was a doctrine developed by a bureaucracy of mandarins,
with "an absolute lack of feeling of a need for salvation or for any
transcendental anchorage for ethics. In its place resides what is substantively
an opportunistic and utilitarian (though aesthetically refined) doctrine
of conventions appropriate to a bureaucratic status group" (p. 476).
In India, the Brahmins developed a secularized religion that suited the
conveniences of the ruling Kshatriya nobility , but were able to remain
as the holders of the rituals, procedures and norms of behavior that presided
over the elite's education and proper conduct. Other forms of religion -
more mystical, inward-looking, magic or salvationist - developed when the
relations between the sacerdotal and the priestly sectors became less integrated.
Buddhism and Jansenism are outstanding examples of salvationist religions
that emerged from the Chinese and Indian traditions, developed within the
intellectual groups, and later spread throughout the masses. In ancient
Judaism, the disorganization of the State and its priesthood, after Solomon,
seems to have given the conditions for the emergence of a popular religion
based on the prophetic movement and what Weber calls "petty bourgeois
and pariah intellectualism," with a strong salvationist and ethical
content.
In other words, intellectuals often are responsible for the development
and maintenance of religious or cultural traditions that lend justification
and social legitimacy to the social order, and in exchange are granted social
honor and prestige, as with the Brahmins and Mandarins. When their prestige
is threatened, or when new intellectual groups emerge they tend to develop
alternative, "salvationist" ideologies and religions that often
preach detachment from the mundane life and the search for inner truth.
The role of scientific, empirically-based knowledge in both instances tends
to be minor.
The discussion of the role of intellectuals in the Arab world is very illuminating
in this respect. The Muslim religious scholar, the "ulama, " traditionally
has placed himself close but well differentiated from the holders of political
power. Sometime after Muhammad, "the religious scholars realized that
by remaining detached from the actual exercise of political power, they
retained prestige without being contaminated by the fault of princes and,
therefore, could better cultivate their intellectual traditions. A tacit
concordat seems to have evolved between the "ulama" and the princes,
" that left to the religious scholars the control of matters relating
to personal status, education and moral behavior."(13) The price to be paid for this concordat was
a hierarchy of different types of knowledge, that placed at its top the
study of religious law, which establishes the proper rules of behavior in
society. In second place came the type of knowledge that could be considered
socially useful, such as medicine and mathematics (which was needed "to
implement the requirements of religious law in certain matters, such as
division of estates and bequests and other business transactions").
Finally, less relevant was the knowledge for its own sake, which could be
approved only because it could eventually help with the performance of useful
social tasks. As Menahem Milson summarizes it, "The order of value
seems clear: the non-religious sciences are considered necessary only as
applied sciences and derive their value from advancing the objectives
of religious law. The value of pure or basic research is subsumed under
applied science, which is itself subservient to religion. '' This order
of priority reflected ''the predominance of the 'ulama' as the uncontested
intellectual elite of the Islamic society" (p. 78).
This arrangement was not incompatible with the flourishing of applied and
scholarly scientific and philosophical work that happened during the medieval
times, through which the Islam culture kept and continued the Greek and
Roman traditions until the Renaissance. The contacts with the West, however,
which intensified after the first military defeats of the Ottoman Empire
at the end of the seventeenth century, seemed to have hampered this tradition.
Attempts were made to modernize Egypt, Turkey and other Islamic countries,
and Western culture provided alternative channels for intellectual development
to the traditional "ulama" religious scholarship. These Westernized
intellectuals were politically oriented, and often tried to reach into the
Islamic past for a bridge between their traditions and the Western ideas
and practices, which were often presented as derived from the Arab culture
in the first place. The main outcome of this process, however, was not Western
science, but political Westernization and Arab nationalism. In this century,
"in the thirties and forties the intellectuals led the struggle for
independence by means of the written and spoken word. They were in the forefront
of the movements which called for complete independence and social reform;
many of them were active in political parties and parliament. But once the
revolutionary regimes were established by military men, these intellectuals
seemed left out. Paradoxically enough, the intense involvement of the modern
Arab intellectuals with political ideology may have contributed to their
political peripherality, once the ideology which they had created triumphed."(14)
The establishment of a Ring Philosopher does not seem to be necessarily,
and not even positively related with the development of modern science.
On the contrary, the Western experience seems to be the product of an unique
arrangement which placed a group of intellectuals in a very special position,
outside the centers of power and with a deep commitment to their task. For
Weber, the explanation goes back to the "pariah intellectualism"
of ancient Judaism, which develops historically into the personal ethics
of "salvation through the believer's efforts," of which the Protestant
ethics and Western rationality are the culmination. Joseph Ben-David, in
the same vein, discusses the traditional roles of philosophers and magicians
in traditional societies, and the question he is concerned with is similar
to Weber's: how can one account for the combination of rationality, individual
intellectual drive and concern with the nature of things that are the characteristics
of modern science. "The traditional philosopher," says Ben-David,
"like the scientist, is interested in grasping, by means of logical
models, some kind of 'reality.' But the paradigmatic reality for the traditional
philosopher was man and/or God. Natural events were not considered as important
as human (or religious) affairs ..."(15)
From this point of view, practical knowledge is seen as a lesser kind of
endeavor, where the search for practical results could easily give rise
to the magic world of astrology, alchemy and shaman medicine. As Ben-David
had shown, the path that led to the development of science as an institutionalized
activity that deals with nature according to the higher principles of reason
has been difficult and irregular. It required the creation of a special
role for the scientists in society, which was different from the one of
priest-philosopher, as well as the one of the magician-practitioner: before
science could become institutionalized there had to emerge a view that scientific
knowledge for its own sake was good for society in the same sense that moral
philosophy was. His work had to be approved and supported, but, in order
to flourish, the scientists should only serve Science, the same that the
capitalist entrepreneur should only serve the requirements of self-fulfillment
through profit and entrepreneurship. Paradoxically, according to the logic
of liberalism, this was, for both, the best way of serving Humanity and
God.
Antithesis: The Kingdom
of Science
a) The rationalization of
society
It should be clear by now that the Platonic ideal of the King philosopher,
as well as the Comtian ideal of the supremacy of "les savants, "
does not belong to the modern mythology of scientism. The liberal notion
of development through rationality is essentially individualistic, and it
assumes that, the same as with the market, society will be more rational
and efficient if each person behaves rationally, and if the irrational and
limiting norms of behavior and institutions that curtail individual initiative
are set aside. It is not a coincidence that Robert K. Merton, following
the Weberian path, sought to establish the links between scientistic ideals
and Protestantism, as an ethics of individual salvation through ascetism
and self- fulfillment. It will be a mistake to believe that the Weberian
model of rational-legal authority through bureaucratic administration is
a departure from this view. For Weber, legal, rational bureaucracies are
rational in a formal sense, that is, they are geared to the maximization
of politically defined goals which are set outside their administrative
realm. The essence of this type of organization is, in Weber's words, "the
belief in the legality of enacted rules and the right of those elevated
to authority under such rules to issue commands"(16)
Whenever this formal rationality conflicts with the substantive goals of
the administration, the first is to prevail, since it is the formal, legal
rationality that gives to the rest of society the conditions for predictability
in the exercise of their private, individually oriented rational actions.
The notion that science, and the scientist (or, in Plato's time, the philosopher)
should govern and impose the principles of rationality upon society is radically
distinct, in that it implies a quite different social role for the scientist,
and a profoundly different way of social organization, in which rational
planning takes the place of the free flow of individual rationality.
The Kingdom of Science is, therefore, in its liberal version, an inseparable
part of the eighteenth and nineteenth-century ideals of evolution and progress
through the development of individual reason and rationality. One of its
central postulates is the radical belief that each person is entitled to
accept or reject truth according to his inner convictions, and that scientific
knowledge should prevail because it was inherently better and more convincing
than conventional wisdom. In this sense, rationalism was in political terms
a libertarian ideology that challenged the traditional organization of societies
and their systems of power and authority. The political significance of
this ideology is much stronger, of course, when their supporters are intellectuals,
university students or other social groups which have a very definite stake
in social change.
Russia in the nineteenth century is an excellent example of this libertarian
function of the scientistic ideology. In his study on Science in Russian
Culture, Alexander Vucinich gives a picture of the ideological and
political climate which surrounded the ideas of science at the time. A group
of intellectuals of the 1860's, among them D. I. Pisarev, N. A. Dobroliubov
and N. G. Chernyshevskii, were the center of a movement known as "Nihilism,
" which was an explicit and coherent defense of the intellectual power
of science and the humanistic qualities of the scientific attitude."(17)
Referring to another contemporary, M. A. Antonovich, Vucinich says that
"he saw in the omnipotence of science a guide to a better way of life.
His idea that all the sciences were part of the same logical continuum led
him to justify the application of natural scientific methods to the study
of society, history and the human mind. His philosophy was a thinly veiled
attack on contemporary theological thought as the ideological arm of a social
system based on autocracy, widespread illiteracy and serfdom (...) The materialistic
concept of the unity of science, the historical relativity of scientific
laws, and the intellectual superiority of the scientific spirit were parts
of a new ideology, which undermined the autocratic system and speeded its
downfall" (p. 20). In its purest form, this ideology did not lead simply
to the rejection of the Russian established authority, but of authority
as such. A law professor at the St. Petersburg University is quoted as saying
to his students that the universities were places where "every authority
is pushed aside, so that the truth can begin to speak for itself.
In its modern orientation, science is independent, just as truth is independent;
it stands above all external interests, all biases and prejudices (...)
it is fearless (...). and self-purposeful (...) it operates on the principle
that truth, which includes everything rational, must be given practical
application sooner or later" (p. 43). The authorities' reaction to
this was, of course, negative, although they were themselves convinced of
the benefits that science could bring to them. Summing up his work, Vucinich
says in his introduction that "the government saw science as indispensable
to the modernization of Russia's economy, armed forces and the public services";
but it also "distrusted the scientific spirit, with its critical attitude
towards authority, its relativistic interpretation of nature and social
institutions, its individualistic approach to problems, and its belief in
the supreme wisdom of man's rational capacities. The authorities had good
reason for their distrust, since nearly all the regime's leading opponents
explicitly expected science to play a major role in liberating Russia from
the feudal past and introducing an age of civil liberty, social equality
and freedom of thought."
This does not mean, of course, that all scientists shared the same belief.
It is not a coincidence that some of the most outspoken supporters of science
as an instrument for social change and modernization were not natural scientists,
but philosophers, law professors, intellectuals. The traditional St. Petersburg
Academy of Sciences, founded in the early eighteenth century, had a vested
interest in science as an independent and pure intellectual activity. In
doing that, the Academicians opposed both the adoption of new scientific
ideas and the social and political ideologies that accompanied them. In
the universities, however, the drive for modernization and change was much
more intense: "university professors were more in tune with the great
changes of the sixties and seventies; to them, the search for knowledge
and the active diffusion of modern ideas were vital tasks of immediate social
importance. It was the university professor rather than the Academician
who introduced Darwinism to Russian audiences, made the names of Liebig,
Bunsen, Helmholtz, and Ludwig as respected in Russia as they were in Germany
(...) It was the professor, not the Academician, who helped science to reach
the larger community as both a body of knowledge and a powerful ideological
weapon" (pp. 75-76). It is an irony that it was the Academy, and not
the universities, that provided the basis for the Soviet scientific establishment
of today.
b) The Republic of Science
"The Republic of Science, ' said Michael Polanyi, "is a Republic
of Explorers.(18) "They explore the
unknown, and are committed only to their curiosity and to the search for
intellectual satisfaction. They are not loyal to God, country nor wealth,
but only to themselves. Each one is free to follow his inner drives. As
in a market place, they "sell" their products as publications,
and are "paid"' in terms of academic prestige and influence. As
in the market, individual rationality leads the scientist to work in the
topics that are more valuable, that is, that give more prestige, and in
which have more comparative advantages, in terms of previous background
and intellectual skills. If he fails in choosing the most rational topic
for research, he will soon be expelled from the market by the competition.
Thus, the Republic of Science fosters individual rationality, and in doing
so, it fosters science as a whole. The aggregation of so many individual
decisions does not result in chaos, but in coherence: a scientific community
is organized through the principles of "self-coordination by mutual
adjustment" and "discipline under mutual authority." This
community develops, through the rules of the market, common notions of what
is important and what is not, which patterns of behavior are acceptable
and which are not and which are the problems worthwhile pursuing. In other
and more fashionable words, they develop a common paradigm.
The conceptual attractiveness of the myth of the Republic of Science stems
from the intellectual elegance that comes with the market-like model of
social integration; in the real world, it is a good defense of the scientific
community against those that try to tell them what to do. According to this
perspective, only the scientists know what should be done in their research,
and the adjustment between the products of their work and the intellectual
and material needs of mankind will naturally happen, as a matter of course.
It is important to bear in mind that this conception corresponds to the
historical reality of a scientific community that, as Derek de Sola Price
has shown, grows geometrically and doubles its size every ten to twenty
years.(19) All the notions of freedom of
research, predominance of truth over authority, support for innovation and
creativity, are closely related with the existence of an expanding frontier
of more people, more resources, more jobs. Science suffers when the limits
for expansion are approached, and questions of priority, precedence, social
relevance, seniority start to emerge. In global terms, only the recent years
seem to be bringing the endless expansion for scientific activities to a
halt; particular cases of scientific centers that reach their prime and
deteriorate for the lack of room or resources to expand are abundant. In
these cases, however, the historian of science tends to look the other way,
to those that had picked up the banner of continuous growth and progress.
The scientific myth illuminates success and progress, and eschews stagnation
and failure. The myth brings also the notion that "there is only one
science," which helps to avoid the problems of priorities and choices
that are not necessary when expansion is continuous. This assumption can
have several different meanings. Here, we are referring to the idea that
science is universal, that medicine, physics, chemistry or political science
have no nationality or ideological creed. For this to be correct, one would
need to have an international scientific community coordinated by market-like
rules in a context of perfect information, in which the production of the
best scientific work would be the currency to bring people to the highest
levels of prestige, control of resources and authority. However, the postace
to the second edition of Khun's book seems to be enough to show that this
Republic does not exist. At closer inspection, scientific communities in
the more strict sense are very small groups, knowledge is hardly transferable
and understandable from one area of specialty to the other, and scientific
research, traditions, styles and emphasis are much less coherent within
any given discipline than what the notion of universal science would require.
The expansion and sophistication of the modern systems of scientific information
have created problems of information overload that tend to limit still further
the possibilities a scientist has of following what is happening outside
his own field of specialization. As a surrogate for integration and coherence
of whole scientific fields, one tends to look at what is being done at the
most prestigious scientific centers and published in the main scientific
journals for an idea of where the frontiers of scientific activities are.
The way science operates in a context of expanding resources was expressed
with all its clarity in a statement of the panel headed by Emanuel R. Piore
which in 1958 reviewed the programs of High Energy Physics in the United
States: "It is not possible to assign relative priorities to various
fields of basic science nor should they be placed in competition. Each science,
at any given time, faces a set of critical problems that require solutions
for continued growth. Sometimes these solutions can be acquired at little
cost; sometimes larger expenditures of funds are needed. Hence, the cost
may not reflect the relative value but rather the need. Each area should
be funded according to these needs" (...)(20)
In fact, of course, this logic of the market does not rule over the decisions
on resource allocation for science, the same as the logic of free competition
does not rule over the distribution of wealth in society. Greensberg's book
on the politics of pure science in the United States shows how, in science
as in other fields, resources are distributed according to the power and
influence of different interest groups as well as political criteria that
have little to do with a clear notion of where the "critical problems"
are. The myth of a scientific market of "critical problems" comes
under stress when science ceases to be cheap and becomes big and expensive,
as it has been happening in the fields of particle physics or the more applied
areas of space technology and cancer research Since the problems of choice
cannot be ignored, there is a tendency to look for science itself as the
source for their solution, in a movement that comes close to the Kingdom
of Science. Nowhere is this attempt to plan science more explicit and naive
than among those that want to bring it to the virgin soil of the developing
countries.
The new synthesis: science, technology
and economic development
The contrast between the myth of the King Philosopher and the myth of the
Kingdom of Science points to two profoundly different perceptions of what
rationality is and how it should and would, in the future, be related to
society. In the first case, rationality is the gift of intellectuals, a
product of their minds , which should be brought to society in a systematic
and deliberate way. In the second, rationality is immanent to social processes,
and therefore should be left to flourish and prevail by its inner strength
and the laws of historical development. They share a common Hegelian conception
of historical development through the progressive unfolding of Reason. But
while in the first thesis rationality should be part of a conscious master
plan for the ordering of society, in the second the development towards
rationality is expected to be natural, pre-ordained and unavoidable. The
first myth is often used to justify ideologies of comprehensive planning
and Systems of technocratic political domination; the second functions often
as ideologies of social, economic and political liberalism and laissez-faire.
Seen from this perspective, it becomes clear that the contrasts between
the two myths of science are nothing but another chapter of much broader
questions of social organization, political freedom and economic planning,
that are the main dilemmas of our time. There are no easy conceptual or
practical solutions to them: this is, after all, what a dilemma is all about.
But it is possible to try to solve them at the level of myths. The new synthesis,
in fact, supposes that science, social engineering, technology, economic
development, all these forms of modern rationality are just parts of one
and the same thing.
Philosophers used to interpret the world, but what matters is to transform
it. With a stroke, Marx denounced the alienated character of abstract, independent
and theoretical thinking, and threw intellectuals, philosophers and scientists
into the political arena. Rationality was a product of social development,
which produced modern capitalism and was to produce socialism. Superior
knowledge was a function of being for or against history, for development
or for stagnation. The frontiers between natural and social sciences, practical
and theoretical thinking, abstract and applied work, were all alienations,
bound to disappear in the very process of social transformation which was
to bring substantive, rather than formal democracy, and concrete, rather
than abstract knowledge.
In a perceptive article written in the still optimistic year of 1961, David
E. Apter remarked how intellectuals and scientists were both distrusted
in the developing countries that were just trying their first steps. "The
intellectuals are suspect: they are politically unreliable; they arc afraid
of drastic social engineering, particularly when they are unduly apprehensive
over the protection of individual liberty." The scientists did not
fare better: "they are also isolated. They create science but they
do not apply it. Their world is the laboratory and the university. It is
the technicians and the entrepreneurs who transform basic science into the
practical products of the world." The strength of Marxism as a political
ideology in these countries was that it claimed to bridge the gap between
the cultural values of the intellectuals and the practical powers of empirical
knowledge. "Insofar as Marxism is a philosophy of science, it is also
a philosophy of social engineering and can therefore be thrust into the
heart of a country such as China to destroy the past in the name of the
future - a process which is also going on in China." Social engineers
and practitioners could bring to these societies their minimum of social
and economic organization, from which a better future could eventually be
built. He perceived a hope for a new culture to emerge in these countries,
based upon a humanistic science, which could blend "the knowledge of
science and the knowledge of social morality." The search for elusive
entities as "negritude" or the "African personality"
was perceived as utopian ideologies that could help to bring this future.
But he conceded that the odds were not favorable, because the leadership
in these countries were not "with the men of science or the literary
intellectuals but with the technicians and politicians determined to build
viable societies."(21)
The fusion of all dimensions of rationality in one unit, to be embodied
by the revolutionary movements and their leaders, left Marxism particularly
disarmed to deal with the problems of technocratic rule, political authoritarianism
and over-bureaucratization which plagued the Soviet Union and other socialist
societies. What happened, of course, was that Socialism did not emerge,
as Marx expected, from the groins of Capitalism, and the intellectual disarray
to have to deal with Socialism in a single, underdeveloped country is still
being felt. This is, as a matter of fact, the main reason why so many well-meant
intellectuals - East or West - refused to accept, for so long, the facts
of Stalinism.
It is possible to say that the liberal, non-Marxist theories of social progress
were not in a much better position to deal with the facts of the modern
forms of technocracy and authoritarianism. Max Weber, as we have seen, shared
with Marx the Hegelian heritage that expected rationality to emerge from
advanced capitalism. He was less optimistic, however, and forebode a future
in which modern bureaucracy would take the reins of political control in
its teeth and bring the modern countries back to the patrimonial bureaucratic
structures of the Empires of the past. There was no place in his system
of thought, as there is not in the Western liberal tradition, for the notion
of modernization and the introduction of rationality that could come about
outside the prescribed roads of capitalist development.(22)
However, after Keynes, economic planning became respectable in the Western
world, and the planning of science and education was conceived as a part
of it. With the works of Theodore Shultz and others, technology began to
be considered as a factor of production on equal footing with labor and
capital, and the concept of "human capital" was put forth, as
embodying the skills and the knowledge that educated and well trained people
brought to economic development. It became theoretically possible to calculate
how much a country should invest in education in order to increase productivity.(23)
Since estimations of the relative size of pure and applied science research
budgets and human resources can be derived from the experience of the developed
countries, they tended to be used as a rationale for resource allocation
in different areas of professional, technical and scientific education.
Thus, planning for science, technology and education was conceived as amenable
to incorporation in models for economic development, and neo-liberal economic
theories joined Marxism in the attempt to build a bridge between the two
poles of the antinomy that contrasted the King Philosopher and the Kingdom
of Science. A basic tenet of both is the identification between science
and technology, which should be seen in some detail.
What is science and what is technology, and how they influence each other,
is one of those conceptual problems that seem to have no solution and have
no purpose besides keeping some writers busy with hair-splitting questions.
Scientists usually know what they do without much questioning, and tend
to use the term "science" as an all embracing concept to describe
the whole field of technical knowledge and its applications. Economists
often assume that science is a kind of lateral or preliminary dimension
of technology, and tend to refer themselves only to the latter, or to Research
& Development, as a unified concept which can, supposedly, be seen and
understood from the standpoint of economic rationality. Their views are,
of course, based on correct readings of important aspects of the historical
reality. Their emphasis, however, on the indifferentiation between these
activities, instead of on their distinctions, is telling.
We should probably start by saying that there is no simple and meaningful
answer to these questions. Otto Mayr, in a recent article, has shown how
the very concept of "science" can change from one time to another,
from one language and culture to another, in such a way that "Wissenschaft,"
for instance, has several connotations that the English word "science"
does not.(24) At the same time, historiography
has examples to show how technology, as practical knowledge, can develop
either from "scientific" knowledge (that is, knowledge developed
without direct practical purposes) or without it; and vice-versa. It is
possible to make some very specific statements about the relations between
science and technology - for instance, contemporary atomic technology is
definitely a product of the Second World War, based on scientific knowledge
developed in the previous decades; on the other hand, the steam engine of
James Watt is from 1769, while the laws of thermodynamics, that presumably
explain it, were only put forth by Rudolph Clausius , Maxwell and others
after 1850. The general question of how knowledge is transferred from one
group and sphere of activity to another is never simple, and duplications,
redundancies, things that "work" without "proper" knowledge
for their reason, branches of knowledge that are developed without any perspective
of practical utilization, all are daily events in the world of science and
technology, with no pre-established rules about their short- or long-range
integration and coherence. Contrary to what is usually held, practical results
are not necessarily the main reason for the scientists' choice of their
problems, nor for the support they receive.(25)
Once it is realized that this is so, it becomes obvious that the question
of the relations between science and technology is less an empirical problem
than a ideological, or normative one; it implies a debate that has been
more or less implicit for many years in the literature of science development
of the last decades.
The dominant view in this debate is that there is no substantial differentiation
between science and technology to justify their treatment as separate and
independent phenomena. An extreme example of this view appears in a recent
Soviet publication, which begins with the assertion that "the scientific
and technological revolution which manifested itself in the mid-twentieth
century grew out of the entire preceding course of development of the world's
productive forces." Two pages later, it is said that "a characteristic
feature of modern science is its industrialization and dependence on the
equipment, apparatus, materials and other means supplied by technology for
success in research and experimentation. Science and technology have always
been very closely connected; throughout history they have mutually influenced
each other."(26) From this point on,
science and technology are taken as a unit, for a rather general discussion
of problems of economic development in the capitalist world.
Jean-Jacques Salomon holds a similar, although more sophisticated, view.
For him, the division between science and technology is a thing of the past,
which reflected the old aristocratic disdain for manual labor, and thus
placed the intellectual activity in a socially superior level than that
of the practical chores. In Europe of the seventeenth century, he says,
there was still a differentiation between "cette science que consiste
a contempler (qui) est réservée aux 'hommes libres', qui font oeuvre 'libérale'
", and the activities of the technician, or craftsman; and, "comme
la technique est au dessous de la science, 1'artisan est au-dessous de l'homme
libre qu'est le savant".(27) The contemporary
nature of science, still for Salomon, was clearly stated by Descartes in
his advice to Cardinal Richelieu: "il faudrait que M. le Cardinal vous
eut laisse deux ou trois des ses millions, pour pouvoir faire toutes les
expériences que seraient nécessaires pour découvrir la nature particulière
de chaque corps; et je ne doute pas qu'on ne peut venir a des grandes connaissances,
que seraient bien plus utiles au public que toutes les victoires qu'on peut
gagner en faisant la guerre."(28)
These two references, selected more or less at random, suffice to typify
the view: science and technology are related and often indistinguishable
activities, and they should be explained, understood and dealt with in terms
of their usefulness for society's goals.(29)
Economic rationality seems, at the first glance, to bring support to this
view. In fact, the adoption of labor-saving techniques can be expected to
result from decisions of private entrepreneurs in situations of labor scarcity
and market competition. In a classic study on the economies of nineteenth-century
England and the United States, H. J. Habakkuk weighs the impact of these
elements with the effects of capital accumulation in affording opportunities
for new methods and techniques to be experimented in the industrial sector
of the two countries. It would be impossible to reproduce here the essential
ideas of his study, but the final conclusion is clear: he talks about the
stocks of ideas available for technological innovations at the time, about
the quality of the educational systems and the skilled labor they provided,
and about how political, social, and psychological factors can influence
the economic efforts in the two countries. He admits that these factors
could have important effects, but at the end he concludes that the relative
lag of Britain in regard to the United States at the time could be explained
"by economic circumstances, by the complexity of her industrial structure
and the slow growth of her output, and ultimately by her early and long
sustained start as an industrial power."(30)
The generalization of this conclusion to other cultural, political and social
contexts could never be done in face of Habakkuk's cautious contention that
non-economic influences are not the best explanation for "Britain and
the U.S.A. in the later nineteenth century. " And even if it could,
it could never be construed as to warrant the theories of economic development
through technology and educational planning.
The stand that scientists take regarding this view is often ambiguous. Whenever
resources are needed, the argument for the broader usefulness of science
appears.(31) Less selfishly, since the Second
World War a growing number of scientists have become impatient and unwilling
to accept the social and political aloofness implied in the ideals of pure
and independent research, as an irresponsible and hypocritical posture.(32)
Before the war, however, the defense of independent and autonomous science
was perceived by many as an important stand in the struggle of freedom of
thought and rationality that was threatened by fascism. In a paper published
in 1938, Robert R. Merton takes Nazi Germany as an example of social hostility
toward science, which in essence "called upon to relinquish adherence
to all institutional norms that, in the opinion of political authorities,
conflict with those of the State. The norms of the scientific ethos must
be sacrificed, insofar as they demand a repudiation of the politically imposed
criteria of scientific validity or of scientific worth."(33)
The attempts of some German scientists to remain away from the political
realities around them only led to passive collaboration, in a context of
dwindling freedom and independence. Others left the country, while some
jumped onto the bandwagon of national-socialism.
Nazi Germany is obviously an extreme case which, seen in retrospect, left
no room for scientific life with a minimum of integrity and coherence.(34)
Merton's conclusion, however , is more general: "as long as the locus
of social power resides in any other institution other than science and
as long as scientists themselves are uncertain of their primary loyalty,
their position becomes tenuous and uncertain".(35)
As a reaction to the attacks on science, he resorts to extreme liberal myth,
which is the one of the Republic of Science.
The search for a middle ground between total subordination of science to
technological and political objectives and the total independence of science
research has led to attempts to devise "rational" criteria for
allocation of resources between the different types of scientific activity.
This discussion is well portrayed in the articles brought together by Edward
Shils in 1968, which started a debate that could not be reproduced here.(36)
Jean- S Jacques Salomon, in a detailed criticism of Alvin Weinberg's suggested
criteria for choice in resources allocation,(37)
asks himself about "what, in sum, is the source for the mythical hope
of objective and rational criteria of choice for the allocation of resources
to sciences." He shows, quite convincingly, that there is no way of
determining the impact of science on economic development in an historical
perspective, and that "even if such a relation could be established,
it would still have to be explained in what conditions the overall research
effort, and more especially non-oriented research, influences economic growth.
The mythology in which science policies are immersed cannot conceal the
fact that there is no necessary relation between a country's prosperity
and the size of its research expenditure" (p. 31).
Salomon's conclusion is that the decisions to support science are basically
political, and are inseparable from the question of the value society places
in science research per se, as well as from the power of the scientific
community as a pressure group. The appeal for "rational," utilitarian
criteria for the determination of science policy is something scientists
do in order to gain support for their independent activities; or, in his
word, "the legitimacy of science conceived as a value in itself is
masked by its recognition as an exchange value." In conclusion, he
exhorts the scientists to give up the myths of the Kingdom of Science, without,
however, taking refuge in their Republic: scientists are citizens like everybody,
and they could "change the orientation of the research effort and make
it more rational and more in line with the universal intentions of scientific
discourse, not by influencing the research system as a means at the service
of the state, but by influencing the ends of the state themselves"
(p. 33).
It is doubtful that science could survive without its myths, the driving
force that provides flesh, blood and passion to an increasingly difficult
and expensive kind of endeavor. But it is good advice to take the myths
for what they are - hopes, wishes, ideal types - so that reality can appear,
instead of its shadow.
Notes
1. Bhabha, H. J. , "Science and the Problems of
Development, " Science 151, February 4, 1966; 541-584.
2. The illicit but persistent marriage between human
rationality, science, and its opposite, myth, has more than once caught
the attention of those who look to science through glasses of the social
sciences. See, for instance, Kalman H. Silvert, The Social Reality of
Scientific Myth (New York: American University Field Staff, 1969) and
Jean-Jacques Salomon, "Science Policy and Its Myths", Public
Policy, 1972, 1, pp. 1-33.
3. Quoted by Bhabha, ibid., p. 542.
4. Contemporary quotations in Robert K. Merton, Science,
Technology and Society in Seventeenth-Century England, Harper, 1970,
p. 27 (first published in 1930).
5. R. K. Merton, "The Puritan Spur to Science"
(initially published as chapter 5 of above) in The Sociology of Science
(Chicago, 1973), p.232.
6. For an historical view of scientism and its role in
the establishment of scientific activities, see Joseph Ben-David, The
Scientist's Role in Society - A Comparative Study (Englewood Cliffs:
Prentice-Hall, 1971).
7. It is enough to refer to the famous Thomas S. Khun
vs. K. S. Popper contraposition of the concepts of normal science as puzzle-solving
activities within paradigms, on one hand, and the demarcation principle
of refutation ,on the other, to draw attention to the problem. The basic
references are K. R. Popper, The Logic of Scientific Discovery
(1934, first edition) and Conjectures and Refutations (1963); T.
S. Khun, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (1962, 1967);
and also the participation of Imre Lakatos, Criticism and the Growth
of Knowledge (with A. Musgrave, 1970).
8. Auguste Comte, Plan des Travaux Scientifiques
Nécessaires pour Réorganiser la Société (Paris, Editions Aubier-Montaigne,
1970; first published in 1822), p. 75.
9. Stevan Dedijer, "Underdeveloped Science in Underdeveloped
Countries," Minerva, II, 1, 1963, p. 64.
10. For a pessimistic view of the achievements of comprehensive
planning in the underdeveloped countries outside the socialist block, see
Naomi Caiden and Aaron Wildawsky, Planning and Budgeting in Poor Countries
(New York, Wiley and Sons, 1974).
11. For a comprehensive interpretation of Weber historical
studies of ancient civilizations, see Reinhardt Bendix, Max Weber -
An Intellectual Portrait (University of California Press, 1978).
12. Max Weber, Economy and Society (New York,
Belmister Press, 1968, 3 volumes), p. 500.
13. Menahem Milson, "Medieval and Modern Intellectual
Traditions in the Arab World" (Daedalus, Summer of 1972),
p. 19. See also Nikki E. Keddie, "Intellectuals in the Modern Middle
East: A Brief Historical Consideration, " ibid. For a more
comprehensive view, see G. E. von Grunebaum, Modern Islam: The Search
for Cultural Identity (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1962).
14. Milson, op. cit. , p. 33.
15. Joseph Ben-David, The Scientist's Role in Society
(Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall, 1971), p. 29.
16. Economy and Society, p. 215.
17. 17.Alexander S. Vucinich, Science in Russian
Culture (Stanford, 1963), p. 15.
18. M. Polanyi, "The Republic of Science, Its Political
and Economic Theory" in Minerva, I, 1, 1962.
Cf. also "The Growth of Science in Society" in Minerva,
IV, 4, 1967; and his major work on the subject, Personal Knowledge -
Towards a Post-Critical Philosophy (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul,
1958).
19. D. J. de Sola Price, Little Science, Big Science
(New York: Columbia University Press, 1963).
20. Piori Panel Report, 1958, High Energy Physics
Program, p.138. Quoted by Daniel S. Greenberg, The Politics of
Pure Science (New York, The New American Library, 1967), p. 231-2).
21. David E. Apter, "New Nations and the Scientific
Revolution" in Bulletin of the Atomic Scientists, vol. 17,
Feb. , 1961, pp. 60-64.
22. For an expanded discussion of this, see S. Schwartzman,
"Back to Weber: Patrimonialism and Corporatism in the Seventies"
by James E. Malloy, ed.
23. Theodore W. Shultz, The Human Capital.
See also Frederick H. Harbison and Charles A. Myers, Education, Manpower
and Economic Growth (New York, McGraw Hill, 1964), and two publications
from the OECD, Forecasting Educational Needs for Economic and Social
Development and Planning Education for Economic and Social Development,
by Herbert S. Parnes (Paris, 1962). Por a discussion of these concepts and
the analysis of the Indian experience on the subject, cf. Trilok
N. Dhar, The Politics of Manpower Training: Graduate Unemployment and
the Planning of Higher Education in India (Calcutta: Minerva Associates
Publications PVT. LTD., 1974).
24. Otto Mayr, "The Science-Technology Relationship
as an Historiographic Problem", Technology and Culture, vol.
17, 4, 1976.
25. The history of Enrico Fermi's research group in
Italy in the 30's shows that support for their work was asked for, among
other things, in the name of the possible benefits of his research. In practice,
however, the only drive of the group was to stand up to the well established
research centers in England, Germany, Denmark and the United States in terms
of their scientific achievements. More important than the practical results
of their research was, for Fascist Italy, what Fermi's scientific achievements
could mean for the glory of the country. Gerald Holton, "Striking Gold
in Science: Fermi's Group and the Recapture of Italy's Place in Physics"
in Minerva XII, 2, April, 1974.
26. A. Shpirt, The Scientific and Technological
Revolution and the Third World. Moscow: Novosti Press Agency Publishing
House, 1972, pp. 3 and 5.
27. Jean-Jacques Salomon, Science et Politique
(Paris, Seuil, 1970), p. 36.
28. Quoted by A. Salomon, ibid, p. 38.
29. The main proponent of this view is, of course, the
British scientist, J. J. Bernal, whose opus magnus, Science in History,
is probably the most ambitious attempt ever made to place the whole evolution
of human science in its historical, political, and economic context with
varying degrees of successes and failures (those being the sections dealing
with sciences in the Soviet Union and with the social sciences in general).
30. H. J. Habakkuk, American and British Technology
in the Nineteenth Century - The Search for Labour-Saving Inventions
(Cambridge, at the University Press, 1967), p. 220.
31. Cf. Daniel S. Greenberg, The Politics of Pure
Science (New York: The New American Library, 1967), for the United
States.
32. For the reaction of the American Scientific community
to the atomic bomb, see Alice Kimball Smith, A Peril and a Hope
(Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1966).
33. Robert K. Merton, "Science and the Social Order",
Philosophy of Science, 5 (1938): 32137. Reprinted in R. K. Merton,
The Sociology of Science (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press,
1973), pp. 254-266.
34. Alan D. Beyerchen, Scientists Under Hitler:
Politics and the Physics Community in the Third Reich (New Haven: Yale
University Press, 1977). For the previous period, Brigitte Schroeder-Gudehus,
"The Argument for the Self- Government and Public Support of Science
in Weimar Germany" in Minerva X, 4; 537-570.
35. Op. cit., p. 266.
36. Criteria for Scientific Development: Public
Policy and National Goals: A Selection of Articles from Minerva (Cambridge,
Mass.: MIT Press, 1968).
37. Alvin Weinberg, "Criteria for Scientific Choice"
in E. Shils, op. cit.; Jean-Jacques Salomon, "Science Policy
and Its Myths: The Allocation of Resources", Public Policy, XX,
1, Winter, 1972.
<